Skip to content

Parispanda

A Peer Reviewed Research Journal of International School for Sree Sankaracharya Studies


Menu
  • Home
  • About Us
  • Editorial Board
  • Current Issue
  • Archieve
  • Submissions
  • Book Reviews
  • Contact Us
Menu

Poetry and Logic: Mahimabhaṭṭa’s Epistemology

Posted on August 6, 2024
Chettiarthodi Rajendran


Mahimabhaṭṭa’s Vyaktiviveka was written with the avowed object of demonstrating that the so called suggested meaning  postulated by Ānandavardhana as the soul  of poetry is actually to be treated as inferred meaning. Inference is a key concept in Indian epistemological tradition discussed at length by earlier philosophers like the Buddhists and the Naiyāyikas. Hence the substantiation ofMahimabhaṭṭa’s thesis naturally   involves a lot of threadbare analysis of the process of inference related to language, an issue which is of pivotal significance to epistemology. This has resulted in theVyaktivivekabecoming one of the few treatises on Sanskrit poetics which have discussed epistemological   issues related to literature in a comprehensive manner. Pramāṇa-s constitute an important   aspect in Mahimabhaṭṭa’s discussion of inference  since the very basis of inference is its validity ascertained through them. The present paper is an attempt to examine the historical evolution of the nature of the three fold pramāṇa-s,  viz., loka, veda and addhyātma mentioned by Mahimabhaṭṭa in his epistemological discussions related to inference(anumāna).

In contrast with the majority of literary theorists  who systematically distinguish creative literature(kāvya) from scientific discourses(śāstras), Mahimabhaṭṭa maintains that kāvya is also can be treated as  a śāstra.[1] The reason implicit in his argument is that poetry, like a śāstra, imparts instruction to the reader  about the  dos (pravṛttis) and the donots (nivṛttis) in life. Mahimabhaṭṭa does not , however, accept the far reaching  implications of this stand that poetry should, like   śāstras  always present valid  knowledge. In fact, he maintains that the test of validity applied to the facts presented in poetry would amount to being ridiculous[2]. However, he seems to contradict himself when he   follows a vigorous methodology in the analysis of all linguistic usage(śābdavyavahāra),  in which he does not seem to make any concession for imaginative literature. From all this, we can conclude that while he is against the application of validity test to the facts presented in imaginative literature, he assumes that even in its realm, literature, being a linguistic communication, has to follow the logical structure of language. Poetry may create an illusion, but the logic of poetic language is that of the language of the real world[3]. 

At the very outset of his epistemological discussions, Mahimabhaṭṭa maintains that the process of inference is present   in the conviction generated by all types of linguistic communication[4]. This statement is very important in that it does not make a distinction between poetic and ordinary languages.   An addresser uses language to persuade or dissuade the addressee; the former wants the latter to do certain things and to abstain from doing certain other things. Now nobody will be convinced about anything unless he/she understands the logic behind it and without generating such conviction, the addressor cannot expect the addressee to act in the manner which we feel desirable. This logical demonstration is the very foundational principle of all linguistic communication. Mahimabhaṭṭa demonstrates with great insight that even seemingly innocuous facts and statements presented in literary languages are carefully orchestrated attempts to substantiate arguments presented overtly or covertly.  A logical relation involves the juxtaposition of probandum, (sādhya)   the thing to be substantiated and probans, (sādhana), the means of its substantiation. It can be represented as ‘smoke, therefore fire’(x, therefore y).  In actual linguistic usage, however, it is only sometimes that their relationship is thus expressly stated; in many instances, a smart listener grasps their latent connection even when it is not explicitly stated[5]. Mahimabhaṭṭa also maintains that in an ordinary sentence, it is the subject (anuvādya) part  which functions as   the probans and the predicate( vidheya) which becomes the probandum. The following sentences ,randomly   extracted from Kālidāsa’s poetry,  could illustrate the relationship  of probans and probandum.

  1. ‘He became the father of the subjects by instilling obedience in them, by protecting them and by ruling them.’
  2. ‘Being eager to meet the daughter of the mountain[Pārvatī], the lord of animals, [Śiva] also spent those [pre-marital] days with great difficulty.’

In the first instances, we can see that fatherhood is substantiated by the instillation of obedience and the like. In the second sentence, the difficulty in spending the days on the part of lord Śiva is substantiated by the fact that he was very eager to meet Pārvatī.

All this logical relationship is at the level of the expressed meaning. Mahimabhaṭṭa maintains that it is the same relationship of probans and probandum also occurs in between the expressed meaning and the so called suggested meaning. The following verse, cited as an instance of suggested meaning (dhvani) by  Ānandavardhana  could be an example of it:

Three men reap the earth

Of its flower of gold

The warrior, the man of learning,

And he who knows to serve[6]

Here the explicit statement of three men harvesting earth of its flower of gold leads one to the inference that ‘prosperity is abundant to these people everywhere’.[7] Here also the relationship is ‘x therefore y’ between the expressed and the implied meanings. The expressed meaning of harvesting the earth of its golden flowers is an impossibility and it causes the inference of  a meaning similar to it. Mahimabhaṭṭa clarifies the process as happening through   subordinate function (upacāravrtti) of the sentence, but it becomes a bit unconvincing since he does not accept upacāraas a separate function apart from inference [8]

It is when dealing with the question of comprehending the invariable concomitance between the probans and the probandum that Mahimabhaṭṭa touches upon the problem of the means of valid knowledge(pramāṇa-s) . According to him, it is through pramāṇa-s   that one comprehends this relationship. In this connection, he mentions three such pramāṇa-s,viz, loka, veda and addhyātma,  reinforcing his argument with  a passage from thecitrābhinaya chapter of Nāṭyaśāstrawhich he quotes anonymously[9]. The passage is translated as follows by Manmohan Ghosh: [10]

The people, the vedas and the spiritual faculty (adhyātma) are known as the three authorities. The drama is mostly based on objects related to the last two ( theveda and the adhyatma).The drama which has origin in the Vedas and the spiritual faculty (adhyatma) and includes [proper] word and meter , succeeds  when it is approved of by the people. Hence the people are considered as the [ultimate] authority on the drama.

However, the reference is beset with a lot of problems as, from the context  it would appear that  the passage does not refer to the comprehension of any inferred meaning at all. It  actually refers to thesepramāṇa-s as the ultimate point of reference in determining the  type of  specific  acting. It is clear that the passage does not describe   the three fold pramāṇa-s  as the authority from which the invariable concomitance of the expressed and the inferred sense is determined. What the passage postulates is the intimate connection between theatre (nāṭya)and the scripture (veda ) on one hand and theatre  and spiritual faculty (adhyātma )on the other and finally between theatre and people(loka) in the judgment of the propriety of acting. 

The three key terms in the original passage also furnish some difficulties in interpretation as the Nāṭyaśāstradoes not care to define them. As to veda, there seems to be no problem since the passage alludes to the intimate connection between nāṭyaand veda, which is regarded as the source of it in the myth related to its origin described in the first chapter of the text. Lokaof course refers to the people at large. The intimate relationship between the behavior of people and histrionic representation in theatre is accounted for in concepts likelokadharmī  in the Nāṭyaśāstra. On the other hand, the term adhyātma  which Dr. Ghosh translates as spiritual remains problematic since the word does not convey any specific meaning applicable to the context.

Abhinavagupta gives a totally different interpretation to the passage.However, the interpretation is not at all very clear and there are many obscurities in the Abhinavabhārati passage.  According to him, loka means the threefold pramāṇa-s  of perception(pratyakṣa), inference(anumāna) and scripture           (āgama) , which tallies with the pramāṇa-s  accepted in his Śaiva metaphysics. If this were the case , the inclusion of veda in the list will be redundant as āgamacoming under loka will have already  covered  it. In order to overcome this difficulty, Abhinavagupta, in an obscure passage appears to have  proposed the interpretation that it is meant to include systems like  archery (dhanurveda ) and music (gāndharvaveda), which are generally treated as Upavedas. [11]His interpretation of adhyātma  also seems to be somewhat different from ‘spiritual’. He seems to suggest that there are certain things grasped through intuition rather than through canonized texts. Thus, while the ‘correlation of word’ , (śabdasamanvayaḥ, probably meaning the appropriateness of the word), can be determined with the help of grammar and lexicon, the accuracy of meter is something grasped intuitively.[12]Abhinava suggests in this context that the elegance of the meter is something understood by oneself; thereupon, basing on this experience, one selects the appropriate melody and language for the song. The whole passage in the end reinforces the importance oflokain drama as śāstra has very limited scope.

When we compare these passages of NāṭyaśāstraandAbhinavabhāratī, with Vyaktiviveka and the commentary of Ruyyaka thereon, we can see that Mahimabhaṭṭa has completely reworked on these concepts of pramāṇa-s  to suit his own epistemological requirements. In his concept, there is a sea change in the very notion and function of these pramāṇa-s  . Unlike the Nāṭyaśāstra notion, these pramāṇa-s  are not reference points to acting; on the other hand, they are adduced as the ground on which the invariable concomitance between  the probans and the  probandum  is determined. Mahimabhaṭṭa also gives clear-cut definition of every pramāṇa. Thus, lokasignifies that which  encompasses anything  well known in the world. Veda has an extended significance as it constitutes not only the vedas, but  itihāsas, purāṇas, dharmaśastrasetc, which ‘owe their origin to vedas.’[13]  According to Mahimabhaṭṭa, veda thus   refers to anything  well known only in the domain of knowledge systems. According to Ruyyaka, this two fold  distinction is intended to distinguish between  textualised knowledge and mere folk knowledge not couched in texts.[14]Mahimabhaṭṭa’s definition of ahhyātma is not clear. It is described as that which comes within the purview of the ‘soul’(ādhyātmikārthaviṣayam), but Ruyyaka unambiguously interprets it as direct perception(pratyakṣa). He further clarifies the position that through this list, actually two means of valid knowledge are accepted, viz., perception and scripture, with the latter further distinguished into textualised and non- textualised forms.[15]According to Ruyyaka, the omission of inference in the list is simply the fact that it is for the sake of  inference that the assistance of other pramāṇa-s is sought.

A perusal of the profuse illustrations given by Mahimabhaṭṭa for the three foldpramāṇa-s   will convince us that whichever may be the source utilized by him, he has been able to build up a consistent epistemological structure on the basis of it. According to him, the so called language is able to convince the reader of the validity of the substantiated facts with the help of the implicit logic we have already internalized through our previous direct perception and traditional acquired fund of knowledge available through textualised or oral sources.

Let us take up some examples cited in Dhvanyālokaand  discussed by Mahimabhaṭṭa.The first verse furnishes an example where the invariable concomitance is grasped from the world.

Go your rounds freely, gentle monk;

The little dog is gone.

Just today from the thickets of the Godā

Came a fearsome lion and killed him[16]

            The verse   represents the words of a lady addressed to a mendicant who was plucking flowers from a beautiful creeper bough on riverside where the lady had promised to meet her lover. She wants the mendicant to go away from the place and accomplishes her objective in a covert way. All that she tells him is that he can wander freely there since the dog which was a menace has been killed by the terrible lion living on the banks of the river. Here the discerning reader cancels the expressed meaning and understands that the verse means exactly the opposite. The probans prompting the inference is the presence of an animal which is fiercer than the dog. One understands that for a person who is afraid of a dog will definitely be wary of a fiercer animal.The relationship between the two facts is understood from the ‘world’(loka).

Mahimabhaṭṭa has furnished several examples of suggestive poetry wherein the implicit invariable concomitance of the probansand theprobandum is grasped through directt perception.

Go, and let the sighs and tears

Be mine ;nor let them rise

from you as well, tortured

being without her, by your hateful courtesy.[17]

In the above example, the wronged heroine tells the hero, who had offended her by making love to another girl, to go away from her since she does not want to make the other girl also  miserable. Here though Mahimabhaṭṭa maintains that  the same results  proposed in the dhvani theory can be obtained by applying inference, the inferred meaning according to his interpretation is different from what Abhinavagupta  demonstrates in his interpretation. According to him, the inferred meaning is that the hero has come there out of sheer courtesy [of pretending ] to maintain their former relationship and actually he is a hypocrite.[18] But in Mahimabhaṭṭa’s interpretation, the meaning inferred is that the hero is in love with the other girl. This is prompted by the fact that on being separated from her, he may have symptoms of separation like deep sigh and weeping. The invariable concomitance between love and the pangs of separation is understood by a reader through direct experience.

It is somewhat intriguing that of the forty-six verses taken up for discussion from Dhvanyāloka, there is not a single instance wherein Mahimabhaṭṭa has taken recourse to veda  to substantiate  the invariable concomitance of the probans and the probandum. However, we are fortunate in recovering one verse of explicit probans/probandum   at the expressed level authenticated by veda. In this verse, occurring in Kumārasambhava, Kālidāsa states that Himālaya was not in a position to make Śiva accept his daughter as the latter had not asked for her hand. Here, Mahimabhaṭṭa states that the invariable relationship between ‘not being asked’ and ‘not capable of giving away  the  daughter’ is known through veda. Here he cites the following verse  from an anonymous source, which in all probability could be some version of the Mahabharata.

O the descendant of Bharata! All things are to be given unasked. Food,  knowledge and a maiden are not  to be given to people unless they ask for them. [19]

From all this, it can be seen that Mahimabhaṭṭa has shaped an epistemological structure using material from theNāṭyaśāstra   selectively and modifying them so as to suit his requirements.  His eclectical project will be more clear if we consider that it is the inferential structure of the Buddhists which he deploys to counter the dhvani theory, as he uses concepts like identity (tādātmya) and causal relationship (tadutpatti) as the basis of invariable concomitance  like the Buddhists and not mere invariable presence of the probans and probandum[20]. But Mahimabhaṭṭa holds all the cards close to him and does not find it incongruous to accept Veda as a pramāṇa, even while making use of Buddhist logic in his epistemology.

Bibliography

Abhinavagupta 1987 Abhinavabhāratī,Vol. III, Delhi: Parimal  Publications.

Ingalls, Daniel H.H , Masson, Jeffrey Moussaieff  and Patwardhan, M.V. 1990. The Dhvanyāloka of Ānandavardhana with the Locana of Abhinavagupta. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

Ghosh, Manmohan 1950 The Natyasastra of Bharatamuni English translation, Vol I.Calcutta: The Royal Asiatic Society of Bengal.

Mahimabhaṭṭa, Vyaktiviveka, (Ed.Prof.Rewaprasada Dwivedi) with a Sanskrit commentary of Rājanaka Ruyyaka.1982:Varanasi: Chowkhambha Sanskrit Sansthan

Rajendran,C.1989.  ‘Mahimabhaṭṭa’s concept of poetry as a Śāstra’, Brahmavidya, The Adyar Library Bulletin, Vol.53, pp113-120

Rajendran, C. Is Rasa an Illusion? A study in Mahimabhaṭṭa’s Aesthetics Brahmavidya pp.221-237

Rajendran, C. ‘Influence of Buddhist Philosophy on Mahimabhaṭṭa’ S.V.U Oriental Journal, XLI,pp. 52-65

Rajendran, C. (2003). Vyaktiviveka: A Critical Study. Delhi: New Bharatiya Book Corporation.


[1]kāvyasyāpi śāstratvam pratipāditam eva, Vyaktiviveka, p.483.See also C.Rajendran, ‘Mahimabhaṭṭa’s concept of poetry as a Śastra’, Brahmavidya, The Adyar Library Bulletin, Vol.53, pp113-120

[2]kāvyaviṣaye  ca vācyavyṅgyānām satyāsatyavicāro nirupayoga eveti  tattra pramāṇāntaraparīkṣā  upahāsāya eva sampadyate iti.Vyaktiviveka, p.78

[3] See, for details, Rajendran, C.  ‘ Is Rasa an Illusion? A study in Mahimabhatta’s Aesthetics’ Brahmavidya Vol. 68-70  pp.221-237.

[4]sarva eva hi śabdo vyavahāraḥ  sādhyasādhanabhāvagarbhatayā prāyeṇānumānarūpo’vagantavyaḥ Vyaktiviveka, p.27.

[5]

[6]Mahābhārata 5.35.64, translation by Ingalls et.al, The Dhvanyāloka of Ānandavardhana with the Locana of Abhinavagupta,p.173

[7]Vyaktiviveka, p.57.

[8]Vyaktiviveka, p.473

[9] I remember with gratitude that it was Professor K.Krishnamoorthy invited my attention to the Nāṭyaśāstra passage in a personal conversation way back in 1980

[10] Manmohan Ghosh, Nāṭyaśāstra, English translation, Vol I, p. 509

[11]Abhinavabharati,Vol. III, p.278

[12] Ibid.

[13]vedagrahaṇm itihāsapurāṇadharmaśāstrādyupalakṣaṇam teṣām tanmūlatvopagamāt,.Vyaktiviveka, p.53.

[14]Ruyyaka, Vyaktivivekavyākhyāna, p.53.

[15] Ibid.

[16]Sattasi, 2.75, Translation by Ingalls et.al, The Dhvanyāloka of Ānandavardhana with the Locana of Abhinavagupta, p.83

[17]Ingalls et.al, The Dhvanyāloka of Ānandavardhana with the Locana of Abhinavagupta,p.100

[18] Ibid, p.101

[19]Vyaktiviveka, p.53.

[20] See for details, C.Rajendran, ‘Influence of Buddhist Philosophy on Mahimabhaṭṭa,’ S.V.U Oriental Journal, XLI,pp. 52-65

Download PDF

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

  • Our Contributors
  • The Task of Expressing the Ineffable: Śaṅkarā’s Tryst with Language
  • Poetry and Logic: Mahimabhaṭṭa’s Epistemology
  • A Śaṅkaran Engagement with David Chalmers on Reality and Consciousness
  • Revisiting Indian Identity – A Cultural Perspective
  • Varṇasamāmnāya in Agnipurāṇa – A Study
  • Borrowing Buddhist Insights to Empower Cognitive Science
  • Some Anti-Metaphysical Tendencies in Indian Philosophy
  • Hermeneutics of Sankara
  • Dravya – Enduring or Momentary
  • Nagarjuna’s Arguments for Relativism in Cognitive Matters
  • Means of Ascertaining Vyapti According to Navya Nyaya     
  • Bimal K Matilal: A Retrospect and Homagé
  • A Śaṅkaran Engagement with David Chalmers on Reality and Consciousness
  • Guidelines to Contributors
  • Adhikaritva in Advaita Vedanta
  • Note from the Editor’s Desk
  • Poetry and Logic: Mahimabhaṭṭa’s Epistemology

Authors

  • Chettiarthodi Rajendran

  • T.Narayanan Kutty

  • Purushottama Bilimoria

  • Anand Jayprakash Vaidya

  • Abha Singh

  • S. Panneerselvam

  • Raghunath Ghosh

  • Saroj Kanta Kar

  • S.Usha

  • Sreekala M. Nair

  • Pradeep P. Gokhale

  • M.Uma Maheswari

  • Remya.C

  • Important Links:
  • University Website
  • ISSS
  • To Contact Us:
  • Call 0484-2463380 (613)
  • email parispanda@ssus.ac.in
  • or iss@ssus.ac.in
©2025 Parispanda | Design: SSUS